Mostrando entradas con la etiqueta Valoración. Mostrar todas las entradas
Mostrando entradas con la etiqueta Valoración. Mostrar todas las entradas

martes, 20 de junio de 2023

El triunfo de los hipócritas

 


On being honest about dishonesty: The social costs of taking nuanced (but realistic) moral stances.

Huppert, E., Herzog, N., Landy, J. F., & Levine, E. (2023). On being honest about dishonesty: The social costs of taking nuanced (but realistic) moral stances. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology. Advance online publication. https://doi.org/10.1037/pspa0000340

Despite the well-documented costs of word–deed misalignment, hypocrisy permeates our personal, professional, and political lives. Why? We explore one potential explanation: the costs of moral flexibility can outweigh the costs of hypocrisy, making hypocritical moral absolutism a preferred social strategy to admissions of moral nuance. We study this phenomenon in the context of honesty. Across six studies (total N = 3545), we find that communicators who take flexible honesty stances (“It is sometimes okay to lie”) that align with their behavior are penalized more than hypocritical communicators who take absolute honesty stances (“It is never okay to lie”) that they fail to uphold. Although few people take absolute stances against deception themselves, they are more trusting of communicators who take absolute honesty stances, relative to flexible honesty stances, because they perceive absolute stances as reliable signals of communicators’ likelihood of engaging in future honesty, regardless of inconsistent behavior. Importantly, communicators—including U.S. government officials—also anticipate the costs of flexibility. This research deepens our understanding of the psychology of honesty and helps explain the persistence of hypocrisy in our social world. (PsycInfo Database Record (c) 2023 APA, all rights reserved)

 

 

Kurzban, Robert. "Why Everyone (else) Is a Hypocrite." Video lecture. YouTube (JamesRandiFoundation) 5 Sept. 2014.*

         https://youtu.be/IcRYrlq--Wg

         2018

 

Wright, Robert, and Robert Kurzban. "The Wright Show: [Why Everyone (else) Is a Hypocrite]. YouTube (MeaningofLife.tv) 2 Nov. 2016.*

         https://youtu.be/HYeyKcDbl5I

         2018

 


martes, 13 de marzo de 2018

Retropost #2054 (13 de marzo de 2008): Algunas verdades objetivas


20080313100341-2317491750-ff27f5ff06-m.jpg
 

Comentario puesto en una discusión sobre si es posible la objetividad, o si se puede contar la verdad tal como es, especialmente en los medios de comunicación...

Claro que existe la objetividad, todo el rato. Cada vez que estamos de acuerdo con alguien en algo. Si un titular dice "El PSOE gana las elecciones", y yo estoy de acuerdo en que en efecto el PSOE ha ganado las elecciones, pues entonces el titular es objetivo. Para mí.

Bueno, que ya os oigo: "Ah, pero es objetivo para tí. No objetivo en sí. Ni objetivo para todo el mundo. O sea, no es objetivo."

Bueno, es que hablando de fenómenos significativos, no tiene sentido el "en sí". Es "para alguien." El titular "en sí" son manchas de tinta en papel, o ni siquiera eso.

En cuanto a que lo que yo considero objetivo no es objetivo "para todos"... pues claro. Existe la verdad, como la objetividad, pero no es la misma para todos. Lo que es verdad o no, lo que es objetivo o no, se determina mediante acuerdos en comunidades. Comunidades de gente que comparte esa verdad o gente para quien algo es un dato objetivo y no una apreciación subjetiva.

¿Que esa verdad que yo comparto con mi comunidad será una falsedad para un tercero? ¿Que esa objetividad que yo señalo será señalada por un tercero como engañosa o subjetiva? Sin duda. Pero también habrá, seguramente, quien esté de acuerdo conmigo y comparta esa apreciación de las cosas.

Por disentir un poco más de lo dicho, diré que yo opino lo contrario también en esta cuestión: que no se puede redactar una noticia de manera neutra y veraz (para todo el mundo, se entiende), "esto es, sin carga ideológica". Eso sí que es el país de Nunca Jamás... yo, al menos, le veré carga ideológica a cualquier cosa que puedas decir.

En suma, que objetividad y subjetividad no son tan distintas como se pintan a veces. Y que por supuesto existen las verdades, aunque algunas sean falsas, y las objetividades, aunque otros las denuncien como subjetivas.

Y hasta habrá quien se deje convencer por mis verdades y mi manera de ver las cosas, o me convenza de la suya. Pero eso ya es otra cuestión, y otra verdad.

Arcadi Espada da muchas vueltas en su blog a la diferencia entre hechos y valoraciones, y defiende a capa y Espada la necesidad de la objetividad en la exposición de hechos. Aunque a mi entender traza una línea demasiado nítida (inexistente de hecho, o según mi valoración) entre hechos y valoraciones.




—oOo—

martes, 12 de julio de 2016

Love of Praise and Love of Praiseworthiness




sidney

A penetrating analysis by Adam Smith on our love of praiseworthiness as distinct from our love of praise.  This is a crucial passage from the Theory of Moral Sentiments ("On the Sense of Duty", II):

Chap. II
Of the love of Praise, and of that of Praise-worthiness; and of the dread of Blame, and of that of Blame-worthiness

Man naturally desires, not only to be loved, but to be lovely; or to be that thing which is the natural and proper object of love. He naturally dreads, not only to be hated, but to be hateful; or to be that thing which is the natural and proper object of hatred. He desires, not only praise, but praise-worthiness; or to be that thing which, though it should be praised by nobody, is, however, the natural and proper object of praise. He dreads, not only blame, but blame-worthiness; or to be that thing which, though it should be blamed by nobody, is, however, the natural and proper object of blame.

The love of praise-worthiness is by no means derived altogether from the love of praise. Those two principles, though they resemble one another, though they are connected, and often blended with one another, are yet, in many respects, distinct and independent of one another.

The love and admiration which we naturally conceive for those whose character and conduct we approve of, necessarily dispose us to desire to become ourselves the objects of the like agreeable sentiments, and to be as amiable and as admirable as those whom we love and admire the most. Emulation, the anxious desire that we ourselves shoul excel, is originally founded in our admiration of the excellence of others. Neither can we be satisfied with being merely admired for what other people are admired. We must at least believe ourselves to be admirable for what they are admirable. But, in order to attain this satisfaction, we must become the impartial spectators of our own character and conduct. We must endeavour to view them with the eyes of other people, or as other people are likely to view them. When seen in this light, if they appear to us as we wish, we are happy and contented. But it greatly confirms this happiness and contentment when we find that other people, viewing them with those very eyes with which we, in imagination only, were endeavouring to view them, see them precisely in the same light in which we ourselves had seen them. Their approbation necessarily confirms our own self-approbation. Their praise necessarily strengthens our own sense of our own praiseworthiness. In this case, so far is the love of praise-worthiness from being derived altogether from that of praise; that the love of praise seems, at least in a great measure, to be derived from that of praise-worthiness.

The most sincere praise can give little pleasure when it cannot be considered as some sort of proof of praise-worthiness. It is by no means sufficient that, from ignorance or mistake, esteem and admiration should, in some way or other, be bestowed upon us. If we are conscious that we do not deserve to be so favourably thought of, and that if the truth were known, we should be regarded with very different sentiments, our satisfaction is far from being complete. The man who applauds us either for actions which we did not perform, or for motives which had no sort of influence upon our conduct, applauds not us, but another person. We can derive no sort of satisfaction from his praises. To us they should be more mortifying than any censure, and should perpetually call to our minds, the most humbling of all reflections, the reflection of what we ought to be, but what we are not. A woman who paints, could derive, one should imagine, but little vanity from the compliments that are paid to her complexion. These, we should expect, ought rather to put her in mind of the sentiments which her real complexion should excite, and mortify her the more by the contrast. To be pleased with such groundless applause is a proof of the most superficial levity and weakness. It is what is properly called vanity, and is the foundation of the most ridiculous and contemptible vices, the vices of affectation and common lying; follies which, if experience did not teach us how common they are, one should imagine the least spark of common sense would save us from. The foolish liar, who endeavours to excite the admiration of the company by the relation of adventures which never had any existence; the important coxcomb, who gives himself airs of rank and distinction which he well knows he has no just pretensions to; are both of them, no doubt, pleased with the applause which they fancy they meet with. But their vanity arises from so gross an illusion of the imagination, that it is difficult to conceive how any rational creature should be imposed upon by it. When they place themselves in the situation of those whom they fancy they have deceived, they are struck with the highest admiration for their own persons. They look upon themselves, not in that light in which, they know, they ought to appear to their companions, but in that in which they believe their companions actually look upon them. Their superficial weakness and trivial folly hinder them from ever turning their eyes inwards, or from seeing themselves in that despicable point of view in which their own consciences must [or should] tell them that they would appear to every body, if the real truth should ever come to be known.

As ignorant and groundless praise can give no solid joy, no satisfaction that will bear any serious examination, so, on the contrary, it often gives ral comfort to reflect, that though no praise should actually be bestowed upon us, our conduct, however, has been such as to deserve it, and has been in every respect suitable to those measures and rules by which praise and approbation are naturally and commonly bestowed. We are pleased, not only with praise, but with having done what is praise-worthy. We are pleased to think that we have rendered ourselves the natural objects of approbation, though no approbation should ever actually be bestowed upon us: and we are mortified to reflect that we have justly [incurred or] merited the blame of those we live with, though that sentiment should never actually be exerted against us. The man who is conscious to himself that he has exactly observed those measures of conduct which experience informs him are generally agreeable, reflects with satisfaction on the propriety of his own behaviour. When he views it in the light in which the impartial spectator would view it, he thoroughly enters into all the motives which influenced it. He looks back upon every part of it with pleasure and approbation, and though mankind whould never be acquainted with what he has done, he regards himself, not so much according to the light in which they actually regard him, as according to that in which they would regard him if they were better informed. He anticipates the applause and admiration which in this case would be bestowed upon him, and he applauds and admires himself by sympathy with sentiments, which do not indeed actually take place, which he knows are the natural and ordinary effects of such conduct, which his imagination strongly connects with it, and which he has acquired a habit of conceiving as something that naturally and in propriety ought to follow from it. Men have [often] voluntarily thrown away life to acquire after death a renown whih they could no longer enjoy. Their imagination, in the mean-time, anticipated that fame which was in future times to be bestowed upon them. Those applauses which they were never to hear rung in their ears; the thoughts of that admiration, whose effects they were never to feel, played about their hearts, banished from their breasts the strongest of all natural fears, and transported them to perform actions which seem almost beyond the reach of human nature. But in point of reality there is surely no great difference between that approbation which is not to be bestowed till we can no longer enjoy it, and that which, indeed is never to be bestowed, but which would be bestowed, if the world was ever made to understand properly the real circumstances of our behaviour. If the one often produces such violent effects, we cannot wonder taht the other should always be highly regarded.

Nature, when she formed man for society, endowed him with an original desire to please, and an original aversion to offend his brethren. She taught him to feel pleasure in their favourable, and pain in their unfavourable regard. She rendered their approbation most flattering and most agreeable to him for its own sake; and their disapprobation most mortifying and most offensive.

But this desire of the approbation, and this aversion to the disapprobation of his brethren, would not alone have rendered him fit for that society for which he was made. Nature, accordingly, has endowed him, not only with a desire of being approved of, but with a desire of being what ought to be approved of; or of being what he himself approves of in other men. The first desire could only have made him wish to appear to be fit for society. The second was necessary in order to rrender him anxious to be really fit. The first could only have prompted him to the affectation of virtue, and to the concealment of vice. The second was necessary in order to inspire him with the real love of virtue, and with the real abhorrence of vice. In every well-formed mind this second desire seems to be the strongest of the two. It is only the weakest and most superficial of mankind who can be much delighted with that praise which they themselves know to be altogether unmerited. A weak man may sometimes be pleased with it, but a wise man rejects it upon all occasions. But, though a wise man feels little pleasure from praise where he knows there is no praise-worthiness, he often feels the highest in doing what he knows to be praise-worthy, though he knows equally well that no praise is ever to be bestowed upon it. To obtain the approbation of mankind, where no approbation is due, can never be an object of any importance to him. To obtain that approbation where it is really due, may sometimes be an object of no great importance to him. But to be that thing which deserves approbation, must always be an object of the highest.

To desire, or even to accept of praise, where no praise is due, can be the effect only of the most contemptible vanity. To desire it where it is really due, is to desire no more than that a most essential act of justice should be done to us. The love of just fame, of true glory, even for its own sake, and independent of any advantage which he can derive from it, is not unworthy even of a wise man. He sometimes, however, neglects, and even despises it; and he is never more apt to do  o than when he has the most perfect assurance of the perfect propriety of every part ofhis own conduct. His self-approbation, in this case, stands in need of no confirmation from the approbation of other men. It is alone sufficient, and he is contented with it. This self-approbation, if not the only, is at least the principal object, about which he can or ought to be anxious. The love of it, is the love of virtue.



End of quote. (TMS, Oxford UP, 1976, 114-16).

Note Smith's careful analysis of the role of point of view and of mind-reading in the generation of moral sentiments, in this case those of praise and praiseworthiness. Not only actual or points of view, or other persons' points of view constructed through our theory of mind, but also virtual, hypothetical, possible (or quite impossible) and non-existent points of view, which have nonetheless an operational psychological role. Social evaluations are constructed in such a way that we shuffle all possible combinations of knowledge about ourselves and about others in order to provide an assessment of our own position and conduct, and of that of our neighbours and peers, should they know about us, for instance, what we know about ourselves. The way they would evaluate us knowing what we know, or the way they would evaluate us were they morally reliable (i.e. their evaluation of our actions as compared to that of an all-seeing God, or a scrupulous conscience). Nobody's point of view, resulting for instance from a blend of our personal information and of the other person's values, is a relevant player in the game of perspectives, just like the actual points of view of our misinformed or benighted friends and fellow beings. Social evaluation is a complex game of masks and perspectives, a play in which naked and unmasked virtual actors play their scenes alongside the real ones. The presentation of the self in social life involves this complex imaginative mutual role-taking, and trying-on of perspectives, in a fairground of multiplying and infinitely receding mirrors.


praiseworthy cicero

All of which brings to mind this discussion on the motivation of human conduct according to Girard, Bourdieu, and Marcel Mauss: René Girard / Pierre Bourdieu: des affinités méconnues. I summarize: according to the second speaker, we are not driven merely by a desire of emulation, as Girard's mimetic theory would lead us to think, or by a desire of being distinguished (Bourdieu's 'la distinction' owes much in this respect to Veblen's discussion of status symbols in The Theory of the Leisure Class). We are driven by a desire for the recognition of our contribution to society (whether the contributions are real or sincerely imagined by us, that's another matter). We want to be valued as value-givers, as creators of positive content, as those who bring a Gift to our peers. That is, we desire to have our praiseworthiness recognized —which is quite congruent with Smith's view.

It is to be presupposed that the Gift which makes us aspire to praiseworthiness is inherently valuable both in the eyes of the giver, and in those of the recipients. Still, some well-meaning and well-received gifts may nonetheless be, in some cases, poisonous gifts. Ask the Germans if you don't trust me.




—oOo—

lunes, 3 de junio de 2013

Los robots se mofan de mí

¿Cómo si no interpretar que aparezca un artículo mío en esta lista de Top Ten Hits?

 
O el siguiente mensaje que me manda, con exceso de celo, el sistema pensante de ScoopIt:

 



Como para inspirar una crisis de productividad. Me viene al pelo, en estas circunstancias, esta reflexión de la pintora Leah que cuenta Mark Freeman en Hindsight:

Leah had come to realize that nothing was essential, that there was no foundation or ground for a painting's existence, no identifiable set of ingredients or qualities that would proclaim its necessity. Along these lines, perhaps there was no identifiable reason for her, or anyone else, to paint. Here she was, creating essentially useless objects that had no discernible rationale, no reason for being. Should she continue to create art? Was she an artist? An artistic breakdown eventually would occur. She would be rendered mute, reduced to silence.

No digo que hacer blogs sea arte, pero bueno, como analogía igual vale. Expresionismo abstracto quizá sí sea.

 
 
—oOo—

Mi fotoblog

Mi fotoblog
se puede ver haciendo clic en la foto ésta de Termineitor. Y hay más enlaces a cosas mías al pie de esta página.